We take philosophical journeys on this blog more than occasionally (the nature of the topic demands it). And it's been a quiet train-journey pleasure to read a paper from Steven Overell of the Work Foundation, titled 'Work and the human claim to uniqueness: A contribution to the philosophy of work'. His aim is to explore "what exactly is it that separates the work of human beings from the ‘work-like behaviour’ of many animals such as birds building nests or bees building hives".
Overell's argument is careful, well-referenced and clear. But reading him from a play-centric perspective highlights some interesting gaps.
In work, there needs to be an ultimate purpose to the activity that is more essential than the activity itself, otherwise the difference between play and work would be difficult to fathom. If ever work becomes an ‘end-in-itself’ it must by its nature stop being work and become something else.
These days, it's an unsophisticated account of play that keeps it confined to a definition as "activity-without-a-definite-purpose" (though it is of course that also). What of gambling/ financial speculation, or team sports, or social celebration, or the serious games movement, or child-centered pedagogies? As Brian Sutton-Smith has helped us to see, our play is essentially a range of "adaptive potentiations" - a mimicking or mocking of social reality so we can survive and thrive better in it. And some of that play will be pointless and an 'end-in-itself' - but some of it will be very "goal-directed" and "outcome-oriented" indeed, though always occuring in its own set-apart play-space and play-time. (As many of those toiling away in the salt-mines of their multiplayer online games will tell you, there can be a lot of labour in game-play).
Overell worries at the end of his paper that we only separate ourselves off from the "work of animals" by an act of arbritrary cultural definition. We use our language and intelligence to tell ourselves stories about and add values to, the purposeful activity of our lives - and we tend to call that "work".
Well, some of us want to argue that, in these immensely productive and technologically transformative times, we could instead call some of that purposeful activity "play", and some of it "care". Play to characterise how we extend the potentialities of our networks, our computers, our genomics, our materials and bio-science. Care to characterise how we extend the benefits of our productive play to all in the human community, recognising that fraility and dependency (not just humanity, but nature too) is what brings moral measure to our vigorous experimentation.
Is this mere semantics? Overell almost admits, in closing, that his freighting of work with so many meanings almost dethrones its centrality for him:
The point here is not that work is directly central to human beings so much as indirectly so: what human beings need is meaning, purposive action, content for one’s life, structures for one’s time, paths to one’s goals, the accumulated habits of social interaction, and finding such things has always tended to accord a primary role to work. It is meaning that is the fundamental need, not work; but work is the vehicle through which meaning is created. Life without it is life-less.
Really? We might not just add 'play' or 'care' to those capacities which keep life from being life-less, but also 'love', 'sex', 'education', 'inner peace' ... The paths to meaning are various and multi-levelled; they should not be streamed together into one vast, thundering highway, heading under a giant metallic archway called Work. If we choose to freight work with so much of our search for meaning, we can also choose not to.
And if our only solution to an economic slump is to revert to the blindly-accumulative, debt-laden, passively-consumerist habits that got us here in the first place, then perhaps we need to.
Recent Comments